People's Democracy(Weekly Organ of the Communist Party of India (Marxist) |
Vol. XXXVII
No. 30 July 28, 2013 |
The
Revolt against Redistribution
Prabhat
Patnaik
THE proposed food
security measure of the union
government is not only anaemic, in so far as instead of
providing universal
food security, it confines the potential beneficiaries to a
mere 67 percent of
the population, but also discriminatory against states that
actually do have
universal food security. The earlier BPL-APL distinction had
put great strain
on the public distribution system of a state like Kerala
which had been
universal and had ranked among the finest in the world; the
current food
security measure will extend this damage to more states,
like Tripura, where
the PDS as of now also covers the entire population. In the
process of
apparently providing enhanced food security, the centre
would actually
dismantle the food security systems of states that already
have universal or
near universal coverage.
What is striking
however is that even this
anaemic, and in certain instances retrograde, measure is
arousing opposition
from a number of commentators on the grounds that it would
cause an “exit” of
the middle class from the State. This is an argument worth
examining because
one is likely to hear more of it in the days to come.
RESISTING
REDISTRIBUTIVE
MEASURES
The argument goes
as follows. Redistributive
measures impinge on the middle class without bringing any
gains to it. It finds
the tax revenue it provides to the State being spent in ways
that are of no use
to it. It therefore begins to “exit” from the State: it
finds ways of not
paying taxes; and, to offset the taxes it does pay, it takes
advantage of
whatever loopholes it can find in the system to benefit
itself. What is more,
since it is dissatisfied with the quality of services
provided by the State, it
tries to arrange those
services for itself
independently: it forms gated and more or less
self-sufficient communities,
like the many “colonies” in Delhi and Gurgaon, which have
their own security
arrangements, their own generators for ensuring continuous
power supply etc; it
withdraws from public healthcare facilities and turns to
private providers; it
withdraws its children from government schools and sends
them to private
schools; and, if it can, it sends its children abroad for
study and for
settling down. And every such move to insulate itself from
the “poor quality”,
and the vagaries, of the services provided by the State
becomes an additional
justification which it adduces for not paying taxes. Every
few steps towards
“exit” in short encourage further steps towards “exit”; and
we have a cumulative
tendency towards “secession”.
The
argument against redistributive measures by the State says
that this must be
avoided, since it is the most educated and “talented”
people who have a
tendency to “exit” from such a State. The
State therefore must avoid
such redistributive measures as are likely to give rise to
middle class
opposition, which means in effect almost all redistributive
measures.
The argument
justifying this tendency towards
“exit” and warning the State not to do anything that might
aggravate such
“exit” is usually further embellished by referring to
“corruption”. Why should
the middle class pay taxes, it is asked, if those taxes go
to line the pockets
of “corrupt politicians”? And why should the middle class be
asked to pay for
redistributive schemes, since such schemes will only give
rise to even greater
corruption, to money “going down the drain”? Redistributive
measures in other
words are sought to be scuttled by dragging in the
“corruption” prevalent in
the State machinery, because of which anything the State
tries to do for the
poor becomes suspect, and hence a legitimate target for
middle class opposition
to it.
Now, “corruption”
of course must be tackled on
its own. But it cannot be made an argument for preventing
the State from intervening
in favour of the poor. Indeed, since “corruption” itself can
be construed as a
form of “exit”, those lining their pockets having “mentally
seceded” from the
State and hence treating State resources as eminently
stealable for effecting
their private enrichment, justifying “exit” by some on the
grounds of
“corruption” by others becomes a mere self-serving argument.
It becomes
analogous to saying: “why I should I not line my pockets by
withholding tax
payment to the State, since someone else is doing so through
“corruption””?
The tendency to
evade taxes, to enrich oneself
at the expense of the State exchequer, is to be expected
under capitalism where
maximising private gain is supposed to constitute “rational”
behavior, and
indeed the driving force of the system. If maximising
private gain at the
expense of others is what the system enjoins one to do, then
there should be no
cause for surprise if these “others” include the State as
well. What is
surprising however is such behaviour being justified by
writers who claim to be
“liberal”. Because the liberal defence of capitalism has
always been that
pursuit of private gain must be allowed, precisely because
the State exists as
a bulwark against any possible damage it can do to society,
including damage in
the form of acute deprivation for some members of society.
If this bulwark does
not exist then the liberal case for capitalism does not
stand.
Those who argue
against redistribution therefore
are subscribing not to a liberal argument, but to a belief
that no bulwark is
needed against the untrammeled self-seeking that
characterises capitalism, ie,
that everybody in such a society gets what he or she
deserves. This argument it
should be noted is different from the one which says that
such redistributive
measures detract from “growth”, that it is better not to
“fritter” away
resources on “populist schemes” but to use them for
investment which would
enlarge the pie later; and that even if enlarging the pie
itself does not
improve the conditions of the poor, the State can always use
taxes-cum-transfers to improve their conditions, since its
ability for doing so
increases with the size of the pie. The argument now being
floated amounts to
saying that the State should never undertake any
redistributive measures, since
that would simply make the middle classes “exit” the State.
STEADY
SHIFT
IN THE
DISCOURSE
We are thus seeing
a steady shift in the
discourse. First it was argued that State intervention for
redistribution must
be avoided because it detracts from growth, which per se would be quite adequate for improving
the conditions of the
poor through “trickle down”. Then it was argued, when
“trickle down” turned out
to be patently unreal, that the State should avoid
redistribution because it
detracts from growth, which by increasing the size of the
pie, will increase
the amount it can get tomorrow
for
improving the lot of the poor. And now it is argued that the
State must avoid
redistribution because the middle class does not like it,
and, since it
consists of “talented” people, ignoring their wishes will
damage society
(whence it follows that a society in which everybody is left
with what he or
she has got, without any redistribution by the State, must
be an optimal one,
where there is no difference between what a person gets and
what he deserves).
This of course is a
fundamentally
anti-democratic argument, since it amounts to saying that
society and the
polity should be arranged according to the caprices of those
who have the
“exit” option, ie, the rich and the affluent (for whom the
euphemism “middle
class” is used). This view is being aired quite brazenly of
late. The Times of
India was recently asking
its readers whether the tax payers should not have a say in
how the tax
proceeds are spent. Now, asking readers this question
implicitly amounts to
running a campaign for it (as it puts this suggestion into
the minds of readers
who come from the affluent set anyway, and gives
respectability to such a view
which might otherwise have been taboo). But tax payers
deciding on how revenues
are spent entails that the democratically elected government
foregoes the right
to do so. It means that the rich have institutionally a
bigger say than others
in the affairs of the State, which is violative of
democracy. And what is to prevent
their say from taking the form: “do not tax us unless we are
the
beneficiaries”, which is exactly what the “middle class
exit” theories are
advocating?
But these views are
not just anti-democratic;
they are also wrong, which is another way of saying that
democracy is not just
an arbitrary value judgment but an eminently realizable
state of affairs. They
are wrong because the distribution of incomes and assets in
society are neither
transcendentally given, nor in conformity with some unique
optimal pattern. It
is socially determined and hence capable of being shifted
about in accordance
with social priorities. And if there is resistance on the
part of some to the
realization of social priorities as determined by the bulk
of the people, then
taking their assets (and incomes) away from them remains a
feasible option,
since it will not cripple society; other arrangements can be
put in place to
replace them.
This elementary
proposition, which constitutes
the basis for socialism, had been put forward long before
Marx. Hodgskin, an
English socialist who had been a follower of Ricardo, had
stated that while
society could not do without means of production and
subsistence, it did not
need a group of people called capitalists to own them. It
could very well do without
capitalists by having these means of production and
subsistence collectively
owned.
Likewise if the
rich in
The liberal case
always was that this was not
necessary, since taxes and transfers were quite adequate to
bring about
socially desirable income distributions. But if taxes and
transfers are
resisted, then this becomes necessary, which is exactly what
the socialists
have said all along.